Select Page
The Metaphysics of “God Exists”

The Metaphysics of “God Exists”

“Gottlob Frege, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and the early thinkers associated with analytical philosophy of language did not merely delimit an area of work within contemporary thought. They modified the very coordinates that structure the relationship between thought, language, and truth. Their project, anchored in the aspiration for rigor characteristic of the formal sciences, stripped language of all psychological depth, of any expressive or emotional connotation. They reconfigured it as a system governed by rules, subject to logical decomposition, and verifiable through the exact procedures of symbolic mathematics.
This new approach was not a simple methodological refinement. It represented a transformation in the very way of conceiving philosophical discourse. Attention ceased to focus on what the speaker believes they are communicating, on their inner experience or on the existential resonance of the statement. What mattered was the logical form of the propositions, their ability to articulate themselves within a coherent conceptual structure. From this perspective, language ceased to operate as a vehicle of expression and became an instrument of formalization. It was no longer a matter of interpreting meanings, but of examining structures.
In this context, logical analysis was not limited to correcting ambiguities, but imposed normative conditions on meaning. And when this scheme is transferred to the field of metaphysics, the effects are quickly felt. Consider a proposition laden with theological weight and philosophical tradition: “God exists.” Viewed from an analytical perspective, this statement cannot be accepted without a rigorous examination of its elements. What exactly does the term ‘God’ refer to? What is being asserted by the verb “to exist”? And what logical relationship links the two terms?
Scholastic theology, especially in its Thomistic formulation, responds by affirming that in God there is no distinction between essence and existence. It is not a matter of an entity to which being is added as a property; it is a matter of a being whose essence consists in being: esse subsistens. The proposition does not express an external relationship, but an ontological identity. Within it, subject and predicate are confused. However, what was self-evident to medieval metaphysics becomes problematic in the light of modern criticism. Descartes, Hume, and Kant, each from their own perspective, dismantle the claim to uphold ontological statements without first subjecting them to the principles that regulate knowledge. In this new grammar of thinking, it is no longer enough to invoke tradition or appeal to definitions. The proposition “God exists” must prove that it makes sense within a logic that can recognize it as meaningful. Here, a distinction introduced by Frege and articulated more systematically by Bertrand Russell becomes relevant: the difference between first- and second-order predications. In the former, the subject is given as an empirical reality, and the predicate introduces an attributable property. To say “this table is white” presupposes the existence of the object and adds a perceptible quality. In this framework, to assert “this table exists” adds no relevant information. It ratifies what was already assumed. The proposition becomes tautological; its content is exhausted in a reiteration.
Something similar occurs with analytical judgments such as “a triangle has three angles” or “a circle is round.”
In these cases, the predicate is contained in the definition of the subject. No new content is introduced; rather, a truth that is already implicit is made explicit. Their validity is not verified through experience, but through the analysis of concepts. They do not discover or clarify. Second-level predications, on the other hand, disrupt this logic. In these cases, the subject is neither empirically given nor conceptually assured.
To assert “the unicorn exists” is not to attribute a property to the unicorn, but to declare that there is an entity corresponding to that concept. Here, the predicate ‘exists’ is not redundant. It is the point of tension. What is at issue is not the relationship between subject and predicate, but the ontological legitimacy of the subject itself. The proposition “God exists” falls into this zone of ambiguity. It has the form of an assertion, but its subject lacks empirical guarantee and its reference remains uncertain. Defining God as “the necessary being” does not solve the problem. The ontological proof, in any of its formulations, encounters the same objection already raised by Kant. In the Kritik der reinen Vernunft, he denies that existence can be treated as a real predicate. He states this with absolute clarity:
“Existenz ist kein reales Prädikat, d. i. ein Begriff von etwas, was zu dem Begriffe eines Dinges hinzukommen könnte.”
“Existence is not a real predicate, that is, a concept that can be added to the concept of a thing.”
(Critique of Pure Reason, A599/B627)
With this, Kant dismantles the central premise of rationalist theology. Existence does not extend the concept of a thing; it is not added as another property. It is, instead, the act of placing an object in experience. Therefore, “God exists” cannot be presented as an analytical judgment or as an empirical statement. It is found in a liminal region, where the statement has logical form, but its subject does not have a clear ontological status. Hence, according to Kant, its acceptance is not justified theoretically, but ethically. Practical reason—not speculative reason—requires postulating the existence of God as a condition for moral coherence.
It is now appropriate to consider a third mode of predication: that in which there is no addition, but identity. The predicate does not enrich the subject: it reveals it as what it already is. Thomistic metaphysics affirms that God does not possess being as something added: He is being itself. “God is being” is neither an empirical proposition nor a conventional definition. It is an expression of ontological identity. Such a statement does not describe a property: it articulates a unity. But this structure, however solid it may seem conceptually, does not impose itself as evident to finite consciousness. There is no experience that certifies this equivalence, nor any analysis that verifies it. From our perspective, this identity appears as a hypothesis without immediate confirmation. And here the need arises for a fourth category: a form of predication where subject and predicate really coincide, even if this coincidence is not apparent as such to the subject who utters it. Identity is real, but unrecognized.
This figure finds suggestive correspondences in certain non-dualistic doctrines, such as Advaita Vedānta or Mahāyāna Buddhism. There it is affirmed that the separation between the knower and the known is illusory. In this framework, to say “God exists” is not to make a judgment about a distinct entity, but to recognize a unity that is only actualized when the split between subject and object ceases. It is not a logical statement, but a form of knowledge that emerges when consciousness is transformed and recognized as identical to reality.
From a different, though no less demanding, perspective, Martin Heidegger raises a fundamental objection to propositional logic. In Sein und Zeit, being is not a property that can be attributed, nor an object that can be represented. It is the very horizon of manifestation, that which allows something to appear without itself appearing as something. To affirm that “God exists”—from this point of view—is to subject being to the logic of the entity, to treat it as if it were just another object among others. It is, therefore, to fall into the fundamental error of Western metaphysics: to forget the ontological difference.
The notion of ἀλήθεια (aletheia), which Heidegger recovers from Greek, designates not a truth as correspondence, but as un-concealment. Being manifests itself, but does not allow itself to be thematized as content. In this framework, to say “God is being” is not a logical proposition, but an attempt to name that which whose appearance transcends all language. The fourth category of predication, understood here, does not extend logic: it suspends it. It is not a matter of classifying, but of giving space to the unappropriable without reducing it.
The distinction between levels of predication—first level, second level, identity, and limit—should not be understood as a closed system. It functions rather as a philosophical tool for questioning the possible ways of affirming existence. In Kant, it allows us to delimit what can be said meaningfully from theoretical reason. In Heidegger, it points to the very inadequacy of the proposition as a vehicle of being. In both, a shared demand is raised: to think beyond the conditions imposed by language itself.
Perhaps this demand—to say what exceeds saying—encodes the most delicate task of contemporary thought. A philosophy that does not limit itself to repeating inherited formulas, but also does not take refuge in ineffability. A philosophy capable of inhabiting the limit without closing it off.”
Prabhuji
Beyond the language

Beyond the language

Derrida focuses his analysis on Aristotle’s Perì Hermēneías, a treatise that has been the subject of sustained attention in our research. In this text, Aristotle formulates a theory of meaning that establishes a double representational relationship: vocal sounds are signs of psychic states, while written words refer to those sounds. This hierarchy, whose structure seems evident, is based on a supposed essential relationship between voice and soul, which gives oral language ontological precedence over writing.
The Aristotelian conception confers on logos the status of natural and universal expression of a pre-existing interiority. In this framework, language is conceived as an instrument of mediation between subjects, allowing the externalization of given mental contents. The communicative function of language thus presupposes a primacy of meaning over its formulation, which implies that meaning precedes and transcends the sign.
Derrida interrupts this theoretical tradition with a decisive objection: the assertion of an interiority prior to the word implies a metaphysics of presence that reduces language to its representational function. Instead of assuming a pre-figured meaning, he proposes to consider that language configures its own field of signification. It does not express a previous experience, but rather establishes a system of differences whose operation does not refer to an original source. Meaning does not precede the sign; it emerges in the very space of its deferred inscription. This perspective dialogues with the critique developed by Michel Foucault, who in Les mots et les choses shows that language is not essentially linked to things. The relationship between sign and referent can no longer be thought of as a natural correspondence, but as a historical device for the production of knowledge. Given this dislocation, to assert that language translates a state of the soul is to reinstate a logic of representation that Derrida seeks to dismantle. By dismantling the priority of the voice, Derrida challenges the classical notion of the sign, questions the supposed transparency of speech, and displaces the ontological privilege that Western metaphysics had attributed to it. The word does not reflect a given interiority, nor does it constitute a privileged gateway to meaning. Rather, it is the place where meaning is delayed, fractured, and produced without any original guarantee. This conceptual shift radically transforms the status of language: meaning no longer appears as content prior to its formulation, but as an effect generated by differential operations. Writing, in this logic, is not a secondary derivation of the word, but the instance that reveals the impossibility of a full presence of meaning in the sign. Language does not translate a prior order: it configures the only horizon in which signification takes place.
Derrida undertakes a decisive critique of the traditional conception that maintains the existence of an interiority of the soul prior to language, conceived as a self-sufficient source of meaning. This tradition, inherited from Western metaphysics, assigns language a subordinate function as a vehicle for the expression of pre-established content. Under this assumption, language appears as a secondary instrument, responsible for translating a prior and independent state. However, Derrida dismantles this hierarchical relationship. Language does not translate a prior substance: through its deferred functioning, it produces what is retrospectively interpreted as origin. Interiority, far from constituting a pre-linguistic core, emerges as an effect of textual operations. In this sense, the soul, understood as a substrate prior to the sign, turns out to be a position constructed by the signifying dynamic.
This is not to deny the existence of subjectivity, but to show that its articulation does not precede language. Everything that presents itself as immediate has already been filtered through a network of discursive mediations.
Subjectivity does not give rise to language: it is configured within it, under the conditions imposed by the regime of the sign. There is therefore no autonomous psychic instance that determines discourse from outside. Derrida’s famous formula il n’y a pas de hors-texte highlights this shift.
What is denied is not the materiality of the world, but the possibility of a guaranteed reference outside textuality. Meaning does not come from an external point: it is produced in the signifying chain, through the endless play of differences. Each term acquires value solely through its relationship with other signs, never through an immediate link with an extralinguistic reality. This approach dissolves the classical relationship between word and object. The signifier “dog,” for example, does not refer to a univocal entity, but acquires meaning within a structure of differential oppositions. Spoken language, being associated with the voice, creates the illusion of an original presence. Phonation seems to give meaning an immediacy that reinforces its credibility as a reflection of an external reality. Writing, on the other hand, deactivates this illusion. It does not conceal its artificial nature: it exhibits the absence of an ultimate guarantee. Unlike speech, which tends to naturalize its link with the thing, writing refers only to other textual marks. This self-referential character reveals the autonomous functioning of the signifying system. The text does not translate prior content: it constitutes it through differential relationships that exclude any transcendental anchorage. From this perspective, even thought must be understood as a linguistic structure. Thinking does not imply accessing pure mental content, but rather activating a discursive device internally. Silent thought does not escape language: it is articulated through internalized phonetic operations. Consciousness is not external to the text; it is part of its economy. Consequently, there is no outside that precedes or grounds language. All meaning emerges from within the textuality that makes it possible.
In the framework of Derridean philosophy, not only speech and writing, but also thought must be understood as textual configurations. What appears as the origin or content of language is already determined by its inscription in the signifying structure. There is no exterior to the text that can operate as its ultimate foundation. Even instances traditionally conceived as original—the world, divinity, the subject—participate in the internal logic of the discourse that produces them.
The distinction between the text and that which it supposedly refers to is thus dismantled. No extra-textual referent can be legitimized as a primary source of meaning. The statement il n’y a pas de hors-texte does not deny the empirical existence of the world, but it does prevent us from conceiving of it as something accessible outside of semiotic mediation. Once enunciated, even the concept of “God” is subject to the operations of language. There is no divinity prior to or outside the sign. Strictly speaking, all meaning is constituted within the text; outside it, there is nothing that can be said.
A similar thesis can be found in our Retroprogressive Path, where the only ultimate reality is pure consciousness, devoid of form and object. The contents of experience—perceptions, thoughts, emotions—are not substantial entities, but ephemeral manifestations of that absolute consciousness. Thought, considered as the first differentiation within the undifferentiated, can be understood as an operation analogous to that of language: the articulation of the indeterminate into distinguishable modes. However, this convergence should not obscure their structural differences. In Derrida’s thought, language has no stable origin: it functions as a self-generating system of differential references. In contrast, for the Eastern contemplative tradition, language represents a transitory modality of consciousness, which does not come from textuality but transcends it. Being is not generated from semiosis, but from a formless reality prior to all distinction. If in Derrida subjectivity dissolves in the play of signs, in Eastern metaphysics its substantiality is denied on the basis of the emptiness that structures all phenomena.
Both currents coincide, however, in the impossibility of positing an original and independent entity that legitimizes language as representation. There is no self fixed outside the discursive field. Deconstruction points to the absence of a full signifier; Eastern emptiness indicates that all appearance lacks a fixed essence. This absence does not refer to a negation, but to an opening: the condition of possibility of everything that manifests itself. It is not a deficient void, but a non-objectifiable totality: to hen, the One, or the formless Absolute. From this perspective, the consciousness that sustains experience is indistinguishable from the emptiness that constitutes it. Language, in its unfolding, does not refer to autonomous external realities, since these are revealed as effects of the signifying structure itself. Words do not reflect reality: they make it appear as such. Consciousness is only recognized through the marks of language, and these do not refer to a substantial beyond, but to a relational field that sustains them.
In the experiences that different traditions have called nirvāṇa, samādhi, or enlightenment, no discursive truth is accessed, nor is any ultimate proposition formulated. There, thought, sign, and difference cease. Unity cannot be spoken, for every word fractures its immediacy. To realize the One is to annul the instance of the self, to cease speaking, to be nothing.
This ontological silence is also found in the biblical tradition, when it is stated:
כִּי לֹא-יִרְאַנִי הָאָדָם, וָחָי
“For no man shall see me and live”
(Exodus 33:20)
Here, reference is made to the constitutive limit of all experience of the Absolute: seeing God implies the annihilation of the subject. That is why He is the Unnameable. Any attempt to name Him turns Him into an object, thus nullifying His otherness. In this context, the liturgical formula:
הַמַּבְדִּיל בֵּין קֹדֶשׁ לְחוֹל
“He who separates between the holy and the secular”
What Derrida calls “the difference” that marks the threshold between language and its ineffable exterior. An exterior that is neither place nor substance, but an operative nothingness that makes all manifestation possible.
In this speculative horizon, where Derrida’s thought, biblical mysticism, and Eastern metaphysics converge, a non-substantialist ontology emerges. Language does not express essences; it reveals its inability to be founded outside itself. And in that impossibility, paradoxically, the absolute can be glimpsed.”
Prabhuji